Nicolas Marketos
Psychiatrist
nmarketos@gmail.com
Marx's
theory of alienation
In this system workers become increasingly dependent on the capitalists who own the means of production. Just as the worker 'is depressed, therefore, both intellectually and physically, to the level of a machine, and from being a man becomes an abstract activity, so he also becomes more and dependent on every fluctuation in the market price, in the investment of capital and on the whims of the wealthy' (K Marx, Early Writings, op cit, p285). Marx noted:
Marx's asserts that the alienation of the worker means not only that his labour becomes an object, an external existence, but that it exists outside him, independently of him and alien to him, and begins to confront him as an autonomous power (K Marx, Early Writings, p324). For Marx this state of affairs was unique to capitalism. In previous societies those who work harder could usually be expected to have more to consume. Under capitalism, those who work harder increase the power of a hostile system over them. They themselves, and their inner worlds, become poorer. 'The worker becomes an ever cheaper commodity the more goods he creates. When labor is objectified, something peculiar happens to the worker’s emotions: “The more the worker expends himself in work, the more powerful becomes the world of objects which he creates, the poorer he becomes in his inner life, and the less he belongs to himself. The devaluation of the human world increases in direct relation with the increase in value of the world of things'( Rubin, 1975).
The labour process: The second element of alienation Marx identified is a lack of control over the process of production. We have no say over the conditions in which we work and how our work is organised, and how it affects us physically and mentally. This lack of control over the work process transforms our capacity to work creatively into its opposite, so the worker experiences activity as passivity, power as impotence, procreation as emasculation, the worker's own physical and mental energy, as an activity directed against himself, which is independent of him and does not belong to him'. The process of work is not only beyond the control of the workers, it is in the control of forces hostile to them. In addition, as Harry Braverman points out, 'in a society based upon the purchase and sale of labour power, dividing the craft cheapens its individual parts', so the bosses also have an interest in breaking down the labour process into smaller and smaller parts. The resulting rigidly repetitive process buries the individual talents or skills of the worker, as Marx described:
Modern
methods of production have increased the fragmentation of the labour process
since Marx's day. The organisation of modern production is still based on the
methods of the assembly line. Scientific research is used to break the
production process down into its component parts. This has led, firstly, to the
deskilling of white collar jobs and to a situation where managers have a
monopoly of control over the production process (Cox, 1998). The unity of thought and action,
conception and execution, hand and mind, which threatened capitalism from its
beginnings, is now attacked by a systematic dissolution employing all the
resources of science and the various engineering disciplines based upon it'.
(Braverman, 1974). Conditions of work, from the length of the working day to
the space we occupy, are predetermined: 'The entire work operation, down to it
smallest motion, is measured, fitted with training and performance standards -
all entirely in advance'. Workers are treated as machines, with the aim of
transforming the subjective element of labour into objective, measurable,
controlled processes. György
Lukács describes how
the increasingly rationalised and mechanised process of work affects our
consciousness. As the following extract shows, his analysis was prophetic and
gives a strikingly accurate picture of today's white collar work:
Ernst Fischer (1996) pointed out that because of this we do not see each other 'as fellow-men having equal rights, but as superiors or subordinates, as holders of a rank, as a small or large unit of power'. (Fischer, 1996). We are related to each other not as individuals but as representatives of different relations of production, the personification of capital, or land or labour. As Bertell Ollman wrote(1996), 'We do not know each other as individuals, but as extensions of capitalism: "In bourgeois society capital is independent and has individuality, while the living person is dependent and has no individuality".
Reification and alienation are two sides of the phenomenon of commodity fetishism (which Lukács calls the 'objective' and the subjective'): 'Objectively a world of objects and relations between things emerges into being (the world of commodities and their movements on the market). Subjectively, a man's activity becomes estranged from himself, it turns into a commodity which, subject to objectivity of the laws of market, must go its own way independently of man just like any consumer article.'
The basic principle of capitalist commodity production, 'the principle of rationalization based on what is and can be calculated' extends to all fields, including the worker's 'soul', and more broadly, human consciousness. 'Just as the capitalist system continuously produces and reproduces itself economically on higher levels, the structure of reification progressively sinks more deeply, more fatefully and more definitively into the consciousness of man'.
Our human nature: The fourth element is our alienation from what Marx called our species being. What makes us human is our ability to consciously shape the world around us. However, under capitalism our labour is coerced, forced labour. Work bears no relationship to our personal inclinations or our collective interests. The capitalist division of labour massively increased our ability to produce, but those who create the wealth are deprived of its benefits. Marx's descriptions of this process in the Manuscripts are extremely powerful indictments of the system:
White collar employees
The American sociologist C. Wright Mills conducted a major study of alienation in modern society with "White Collar" in 1951, describing how modern social division of labor, involve a hitherto unknown specialization of skill: as a proportion of the labor force, fewer individuals manipulate things, more handle people and symbols. This shift in needed skills is another way of describing the rise of the white-collar workers, for their characteristic skills involve the handling of paper and money and people. They are masters of the commercial, professional, and technical relationship. They live off the social machineries that organize and co-ordinate the people who do make things. White-collar people help turn what someone else has made into profit.
False consciousness
The concept “False consciousness” refers to the systematic misrepresentation of dominant social relations in the consciousness of subordinate classes. Marx himself did not use the phrase “false consciousness,” but he paid extensive attention to the related concepts of ideology and commodity fetishism. Members of a subordinate class (workers, peasants, serfs) suffer from false consciousness in that their mental representations of the social relations around them systematically conceal or obscure the realities of subordination, exploitation, and domination those relations embody. Related concepts include mystification, ideology, and fetishism.
Twentieth-century Marxist thinkers have given more systematic attention to a Marxist theory of consciousness and ideology. Georg Lukács introduces the concept of false consciousness into Marxist discourse, based on a brief reference by Engels, in relation to a dialectical theory of knowledge.
Frantz Fanon: Alienation and colonianism
Frantz Fanon, an early writer on postcolonialism, studied the conditions of objectification and violent oppression (lack of autonomy) believed to have led to mental disorders among the colonized in the Third World (in particular Africans) (Fanon, 1961).
Fanon sees the alienation of the colonized, as essentially socio-economic, but it is a socio-economic (socio-political) alienation that has profound psychological effects. He speaks about the alienation of the Negro in terms of cultural imposition, and of the exploitation of the native by the colonists.
Colonialism is not simply the economic exploitation and political domination of the periphery by the capitalist core. It is also the separation of colonized peoples from their individuality and culture (Fanon 1961).
Racism and its objectification of the colonized, Fanon argues, can only be understood through its connection to capitalism. The colonial relationship between core and periphery in global capitalism is, like that between capitalist and proletariat, based on exploitation/
Epistemological
approaches
Psychoanalytic theory on the concept of alienation, focused on the
divisions and conflicts between the conscious and unconscious mind, between
different parts of a hypothetical psychic apparatus, and between the self and
civilization. It included defense mechanism, of splitting, in both normal and
disturbed functioning. The concept of repression has been described as having
functionally equivalent effects as the idea of false consciousness associated
with Marxist theory (Geyer, 2001).
Horkheimer and Adorno noticed the development of individuals becoming totally subordinated by the economic powers. The question of the character of man is mainly the question of his or her function in society in general and in the economic system in particular. That is what we can call the substitution of character by function.
Finally generating an artificial need for something is a kind of manipulation and so the people get trapped in this so called cycle of manipulation and need. Mass media and culture now is one way to fortify this cycle. The interesting and finally dialectic aspect of this cycle is, what Horkheimer and Adorno also state, that by offering people this kind of mass culture with a lots of choices, it is pretended that capitalist society offers a never seen before freedom for people. But finally it is a just illusory freedom without real alternatives. The freedom is limited to the choice of buying just different sorts of the ever-same. This illusion “of competition and choice” is held up high by the mass media using advertisement and entertaining to keep people at it.
That leads to a direct influence on society. We again come to the point of the character of man. On the one hand it was stated, that it is build up by the role he or she adjusts to in society, on the other hand character is often build up and indicated to the outside world by what one does and what one has. By the clothing one wears he or she mostly automatically indicates belonging to a social group, may it be a group marked by financial status, wearing e.g. luxury brands, or a group marked by an ideological or not seldom musical background, e.g. wearing “hip-hop-style” clothing or Gothic clothing, etc.. But finally showing a belonging to a group by using products produced in the cycle of manipulation and need restrains the categories of character to choose from to a maybe high but still limited number. Individuality is pseudo-individuality. Thus, finally the capitalistic economic system offers us a kind of matrix of possibilities we can fit ourself in, but real freedom remains illusionary. The human will always be just a member of a group, limited in choices. Within this group his character is only in limited ways individual, if it is at all.
The alienation the human being in modern mass society runs through is a dialectic of adjustment and equalisation on the one side and of isolation on the other side.
By becoming a just “functioning part” of society, blunted by the phenomenon of mass culture and the use of an almost mere technological rationality, people loose the ability for real sociality. In Education after Auschwitz Adorno criticises in a very similar way the loss of the ability to love. People become monads, struggling in the social coldness and atmosphere of competition and hostility of everyday life. Alienation becomes finally an all-embracing phenomenon. People are alienated of each other and are trapped in a capitalistic cage, being a mass, which can be directed, e.g. using mass media. Individual critical thinking was substituted by the already described mere technological rationality. Thus, by mass culture and the capitalistic economical system the cornerstone for the fascistic and totalitarian system is laid. Since society was not more than an accumulation of monads, being indifferent against the individual, e.g. the use of technological rationality for realizing a system of industrialised mass murder became eventually possible. The rationality, born by the Enlightenment, reversed itself into the contrary. In Education after Auschwitz Adorno raises the question, how it otherwise could be possible, that e.g. a well-educated engineer uses his knowledge to construct a railway-system for the deportation of Jews to Concentration Camps. This finally was a consequence of alienation from oneself and others.
The result is the promotion of a 'purposive rational action' in all spheres. An action orientated to profit and power rather than understanding, arising from entrepreneurial capitalism.
Modern second-order cybernetics is a paradigm that offer a holistic picture of the constantly emerging novel complexities of ongoing human interaction, and does not postulate simplistic assumptions about the constancy of human behavior. The result of the adoption of the systemic paradigm, is that alienation studies, are becoming less denunciatory, less normative, and moralistic (Geyer, 1998).
The pathology of alienation
Seeman (1959) recognized the problems inherent in defining the "self", while post-modernism in particular has questioned the very possibility of pin-pointing what precisely "self" constitutes. Gergen (1996) argues that: “the traditional view of self versus society is deeply problematic and should be replaced by a conception of the self as always already immersed in relatedness. On this account, the individual’s lament of ‘not belonging’ is partially a by-product of traditional discourses themselves”. If the self is relationally constituted, does it make sense to speak of "self-estrangement" rather than "social isolation"?
Laing was one of the most articulate critics of the stance in which “the clinician assumes a priori that he is a neutral scientific observer/classifier of an (irrational) patient’s speech and behavior.”
Laing must be understood as part of a larger tradition that has raised important questions about the social construction of sanity and about the need for a theory and therapeutic practice that puts un-measurable qualities such as human hope, fears, evil and even spiritual well-being at the center of any psychological approach in the human sciences and helping professions.
Following the flowering of contestation movements at sixties and student revolutions in Europe and the USA, alienation studies proliferated, at least in the Western world. The existence of alienation in the ‘decadent, bourgeois’ societies of the West was confirmed, as it was supposed to herald the impending demise of late capitalism.
Coping
alienation
The above mentioned Bloom’s analysis of employability, seeks to provide the foundations for moving beyond this fantasy of employability. Recently, a number of critical scholars within the field have theorized the relation of fantasy to resistance. Hoedemaekers (2010), for example, calls on subjects to pay attention to such ‘interruptions’ to identification as potential sites for transversing, or break free from, a prevailing fantasy. Similarly, Contu (2008), inspired by Žižek, promotes a form of resistance by which individuals are willing to engage in acts that defy the symbolism and enjoyment associated with their current identities. Specific to discourses of employability, Cremin (2010) suggests to construct new fantasies and therefore selves which reject ideologies of managerialism and exploitation in favour of new values. Indeed, this appears to be happening the world over, as struggles in the wake of the financial crisis, such as the occupy movement or those catalyzed by the European debt crisis, in which new ‘commons’ are emerging reconfiguring identity work in relation to ideals of greater social and economic freedom and democracy.
Major changes in the world as globalization and the computer science and technology revolution have brought to the fore new productive forces and changes in relations of production and explosion of societal complexity and worldwide interdependence.
3Illocutionary pertaining to a linguistic act performed by a speaker in producing an utterance, as suggesting, warning, promising, or requesting. Illocutionary act is a term in linguistics introduced by the philosopher John L. Austin in his investigation of the various aspects of speech acts. For example, in uttering the locution "Is there any salt?" at the dinner table, one may thereby perform the illocutionary act of requesting salt, as well as the distinct locutionary act of uttering the interrogatory sentence about the presence of salt, and the further perlocutionary act of causing somebody to hand one the salt.
Bloom Peter (2013) Fight for your alienation: The fantasy of employability and the ironic struggle for self-exploitation. Ephemera volume 14, number 4 November,
Contu, A.
(2008) ‘Decaf resistance: On misbehavior, cynicism and desire in liberal
workplaces’, Management Communication Quarterly, 21(3): 364-379.
Cremin, C. (2010) ‘Never employable enough: The (im)possibility of satisfying the boss’s desire’, Organization, 17(2): 131-149.
Fanon Frantz (1961), The Wretched of the Earth: A Negro Psychoanalyst’s Study of the Problems of Racism & Colonialism in the World Today. 1961 (New York, New York: Grove Press, Inc.)
Fischer E, (1996) How to Read Karl Marx (Monthly Review Press, 1996)
Geyer Felix (2001) Alienation, Sociology of in International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, Paul Baltes and Neil Smelser, Eds., London: Elsevier Durkheim Alienation, Sociology of
Horkheimer Max, Adorno W. Theodor (1947) Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments Stanford University Press,
Linebaugh P, The London Hanged (Penguin, 1993)
Lukács, G. (1971) History and class consciousness. London: Merlin Press
Lukács, György. 1971 [1920]. History and class consciousness; studies in Marxist dialectics. Cambridge, Mass.,: MIT Press.
Mannheim, Karl. 1959 [1936]. Ideology and utopia : an introduction to the sociology of knowledge, A harvest book ; HB 3. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Schwartz C. David 2007 Political Alienation and Political Behavior Transaction Publishers, 30 Apr 2007 David C. Schwartz Political Alienation and Political Behavior Transaction Publishers, 30 Apr 2007
Psychiatrist
nmarketos@gmail.com
Abstract
This essay examines the definition of alienation, in the sense of a subjective state of separation that occurs in human relationships, in the context of relations of production and of economic system, which affects persons life, and psychology. It presents the Marxist analysis of alienation and the relative concepts of 'reification' 'and' 'commodity fetishism' as well as the concept of 'false consciousness'' described by György Lukács. Frantz Fanon, reported the specific characteristics of alienation in the psyche of the colonized peoples. Twentieth-century theorists of Frankfurt School (notably Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, Erich Fromm and Jürgen Habermas) enriched the Marxist theory of alienation, incorporating new epistemologies and extended it to cultural and sociological field. This paper also refers to the approaches of psychoanalysis, systemic and complexity theory to alienation and examines the psychopathological consequences of alienation at individual and group level, as well as the forms of alienation in today's world of globalization and the development of technology and computer technology. It concludes by suggesting ways to cope with the consequences of alienation.
This essay examines the definition of alienation, in the sense of a subjective state of separation that occurs in human relationships, in the context of relations of production and of economic system, which affects persons life, and psychology. It presents the Marxist analysis of alienation and the relative concepts of 'reification' 'and' 'commodity fetishism' as well as the concept of 'false consciousness'' described by György Lukács. Frantz Fanon, reported the specific characteristics of alienation in the psyche of the colonized peoples. Twentieth-century theorists of Frankfurt School (notably Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, Erich Fromm and Jürgen Habermas) enriched the Marxist theory of alienation, incorporating new epistemologies and extended it to cultural and sociological field. This paper also refers to the approaches of psychoanalysis, systemic and complexity theory to alienation and examines the psychopathological consequences of alienation at individual and group level, as well as the forms of alienation in today's world of globalization and the development of technology and computer technology. It concludes by suggesting ways to cope with the consequences of alienation.
Marx's
theory of alienation
Karl
Marx's theory of alienation describes the social alienation of people from
aspects of their human nature. Alienation is the systemic result of living in a
socially stratified society, because being a mechanistic part of a social class
alienates a person from his and her humanity. The theoretic basis of alienation
within the capitalist mode of production is that the worker invariably loses the
ability to determine his or her life and destiny, when deprived of the right to
think (conceive) of himself as the director of his actions; to define their
relationship with other people; and to own the things and use the value of the
goods and services, produced with their labour. Although the worker is an
autonomous, self-realised human being, as an economic entity, he or she is
directed to goals and diverted to activities that are dictated by the
bourgeoisie, who own the means of production, in order to extract from the
worker the maximum amount of surplus value, in the course of business
competition among industrialists.
Alienation
is a concept, with its roots going back to Roman law, where alienatio was a
legal term used to denote the act of transferring property. St. Augustine
described insanity as abalienatio mentis; Ludz (1975) has discussed its use
among the early Gnostics.
The roots of Marx's critique of alienation may be
found, in Hegel's critique of "positivity and the authoritarianism created
by unchallenged truths. Hegel's concept of alienation is not only a
psychological estrangement, but entails a practical, everyday absence of control
in a world where persons have become passive spectators, incapable of
themselves achieving their own values by their own efforts.
For Hegel, alienation is inherent in human life which
necessarily and everywhere creates the social world by making and using
objects, while making and transforming itself in that very process. At some
point, however, the object world and the inner world are no longer in gear, and
men cease to recognize the object world as having been brought into
existence by their own human activity.
Alienation is a basic
mechanism whereby being is externalized from itself. It comprehends its own externalization
in metaphysical reflection as other and alien. Man (the subjective spirit)
finds himself in a relation where he is mediated by his own objectified
products (the objective spirit); man has the task of overcoming epistemological
alienation by becoming conscious of his identity-in-spirit with his own
products (the illusory character of alienation), and thereby also to discover
the unity of himself, and the world. This end is to be reached by philosophical
knowledge that levels the boundaries between man’s culture and nature.
Ludwig Feuerbach put forward a materialist
analysis of alienation, in
arguing that people
alienate their essential being by attributing their human qualities to a god
who is then worshipped on account of these qualities. Thus Feuerbach argues
that religion is a form of alienation which prevents people from attaining realization
of their own species-being. Feuerbach’s thinking has been described as humanist
in that his theory of alienation is based on a theory of human nature as
species-being, as innate to the human species.
Marx’s
theory of alienation was based upon his observation that capitalism involved ‘’a
fundamental change in the relations between men, instruments of production and
the materials of production'’. (Linebaugh, 1993). These fundamental changes
meant that every aspect of life was transformed.
Men
no longer enjoyed the right to dispose of what they produced how they chose:
they became separated from the product of their labour. The mechanisation of
labour in the factories transformed people's relationship with machines, 'those
remarkable products of human ingenuity, became a source of tyranny against the
worker'(Capital, op cit, p460).
One
of the most important, and devastating, features of factory production was the
division of labour. This division of labour meant that workers had to
specialise in particular tasks, a series of atomised reiterated activities,
which realised only one or two aspects of their human powers at the expense of
all the others.
In this system workers become increasingly dependent on the capitalists who own the means of production. Just as the worker 'is depressed, therefore, both intellectually and physically, to the level of a machine, and from being a man becomes an abstract activity, so he also becomes more and dependent on every fluctuation in the market price, in the investment of capital and on the whims of the wealthy' (K Marx, Early Writings, op cit, p285). Marx noted:
The fact that labour is external to the worker, does not belong to his
essential being; that he therefore does not confirm himself in his work, but
denies himself, feels miserable and not happy, does not develop free mental and
physical energy, but mortifies his flesh and ruins his mind. Hence the worker feels
himself only when he is not working. Its alien character is clearly
demonstrated by the fact that as soon as no physical or other compulsion exists
it is shunned like the plague.
The
development of capitalism proved irresistible and it brought alienation on a
scale previously unimaginable. In his Economic
and Philosophical Manuscripts Marx identified four specific ways in which
alienation pervades capitalist society.
The product of labour: The worker is alienated from the
object he produces because it is owned and disposed of by another, the
capitalist. In all societies people use their creative abilities to produce
objects which they use, exchange or sell. Under capitalism, however, this
becomes an alienated activity because 'the worker cannot use the things he
produces to keep alive or to engage in further productive activity... The
worker's needs, no matter how desperate, do not give him a license to lay hands
on what these same hands have produced, for all his products are the property
of another'(Ollman, 1996). Thus workers produce cash crops for the market when
they are malnourished, build houses in which they will never live, make cars
they can never buy, produce shoes they cannot afford to wear, and so on.
Marx
argued that the alienation of the worker from what he produces is intensified
because the products of labour actually begin to dominate the labourer.
Marx's asserts that the alienation of the worker means not only that his labour becomes an object, an external existence, but that it exists outside him, independently of him and alien to him, and begins to confront him as an autonomous power (K Marx, Early Writings, p324). For Marx this state of affairs was unique to capitalism. In previous societies those who work harder could usually be expected to have more to consume. Under capitalism, those who work harder increase the power of a hostile system over them. They themselves, and their inner worlds, become poorer. 'The worker becomes an ever cheaper commodity the more goods he creates. When labor is objectified, something peculiar happens to the worker’s emotions: “The more the worker expends himself in work, the more powerful becomes the world of objects which he creates, the poorer he becomes in his inner life, and the less he belongs to himself. The devaluation of the human world increases in direct relation with the increase in value of the world of things'( Rubin, 1975).
A
necessary corollary of assessing human worth in economic terms is the elevation
of materialistic values over human values of compassion, skill, or creativity.
Thus, “in the capitalistic hierarchy of values, capital stands higher than
labor, amassed things higher than the manifestations of life.” Humanity is
diminished as qualities such as a person’s energy, skill, personality, and
creativity become commodified—assets to be sold on the market of interpersonal
relations. Under capitalism, “the market decides the value of these human
qualities” with the result that “relations between human beings . . . assume
the character of relations between things,” as each person “sells himself and
feels himself to be a commodity.” (Fromm,
1966).
The labour process: The second element of alienation Marx identified is a lack of control over the process of production. We have no say over the conditions in which we work and how our work is organised, and how it affects us physically and mentally. This lack of control over the work process transforms our capacity to work creatively into its opposite, so the worker experiences activity as passivity, power as impotence, procreation as emasculation, the worker's own physical and mental energy, as an activity directed against himself, which is independent of him and does not belong to him'. The process of work is not only beyond the control of the workers, it is in the control of forces hostile to them. In addition, as Harry Braverman points out, 'in a society based upon the purchase and sale of labour power, dividing the craft cheapens its individual parts', so the bosses also have an interest in breaking down the labour process into smaller and smaller parts. The resulting rigidly repetitive process buries the individual talents or skills of the worker, as Marx described:
Factory work exhausts the nervous system to the uttermost, it does away
with the many-sided play of the muscles, and confiscates every atom of freedom,
both in bodily and intellectual activity... The special skill of each
individual insignificant factory operative vanishes as an infinitesimal
quantity before the science, the gigantic physical forces, and mass of labour
that are embodied in the factory mechanism and, together, with that mechanism,
constitute the power of the master.
In consequence of the rationalisation of the work-process the human
qualities and idiosyncrasies of the worker appear increasingly as mere sources
of error when contrasted with these abstract special laws functioning according
to rational predictions. Neither objectively nor in his relation to his work
does man appear as the authentic master of this process; on the contrary, he is
a mechanical part incorporated into a mechanical system. He finds it already
pre-existing and self-sufficient, it functions independently of him and he has
to conform to its laws whether he likes it or not. (Lukács, 1971).
Human relationships: Thirdly, we are alienated from our
fellow human beings. This alienation arises in part because of the antagonisms
which inevitably arise from the class structure of society. We are alienated
from those who exploit our labour and control the things we produce.
Ernst Fischer (1996) pointed out that because of this we do not see each other 'as fellow-men having equal rights, but as superiors or subordinates, as holders of a rank, as a small or large unit of power'. (Fischer, 1996). We are related to each other not as individuals but as representatives of different relations of production, the personification of capital, or land or labour. As Bertell Ollman wrote(1996), 'We do not know each other as individuals, but as extensions of capitalism: "In bourgeois society capital is independent and has individuality, while the living person is dependent and has no individuality".
Marx
described how mass commodity production continually seeks to create new needs,
not to develop our human powers but to exploit them for profit.
We see other people through the lens of profit and loss. Our abilities and needs are converted into means of making money and so we consider other human beings as competitors, as inferiors or superiors.
We see other people through the lens of profit and loss. Our abilities and needs are converted into means of making money and so we consider other human beings as competitors, as inferiors or superiors.
Human
relationships are distorted by the phenomenon of reification. Reification [res: thing] refers to
the phenomenon of a “definite social relation between men” appearing in the
form of a “relation between things” and thus acquires a ‘phantom objectivity', an autonomy that seems so
strictly rational and all‑embracing as to conceal every trace of its
fundamental nature: the relation between people'. The Phenomenon of reification
is the central structural problem of capitalist society’.
Reification and alienation are two sides of the phenomenon of commodity fetishism (which Lukács calls the 'objective' and the subjective'): 'Objectively a world of objects and relations between things emerges into being (the world of commodities and their movements on the market). Subjectively, a man's activity becomes estranged from himself, it turns into a commodity which, subject to objectivity of the laws of market, must go its own way independently of man just like any consumer article.'
The basic principle of capitalist commodity production, 'the principle of rationalization based on what is and can be calculated' extends to all fields, including the worker's 'soul', and more broadly, human consciousness. 'Just as the capitalist system continuously produces and reproduces itself economically on higher levels, the structure of reification progressively sinks more deeply, more fatefully and more definitively into the consciousness of man'.
The
distinction between a worker faced with a particular machine, the entrepreneur
faced with a given type of mechanical development, the technologist faced with
the state of science and the profitability of its application to technology, is
purely quantitative; it does not directly entail any qualitative
difference in the structure of consciousness.
In describing how
the laws of the market corrupt personal relations, Fromm concludes that human
communication and interpersonal feelings are distorted by the application of a
cost-benefit analysis way of thinking to social relationships: in all social
and personal relations the laws of the market are the rule. The logic of the
exchange economy pervades all aspects of life, because in capitalistic society
the process of exchange value has become an end in itself; thus, the whole
process of living is experienced analogously to the profitable investment of
capital, my life and my person being the capital which is invested.
Our human nature: The fourth element is our alienation from what Marx called our species being. What makes us human is our ability to consciously shape the world around us. However, under capitalism our labour is coerced, forced labour. Work bears no relationship to our personal inclinations or our collective interests. The capitalist division of labour massively increased our ability to produce, but those who create the wealth are deprived of its benefits. Marx's descriptions of this process in the Manuscripts are extremely powerful indictments of the system:
It is true that labour produces marvels for the rich, but it produces
privation for the worker. It produces palaces, but hovels for the worker. It
procures beauty, but deformity for the worker. It replaces labour by machines,
but it casts some of the workers back into barbarous forms of labour and turns
others into machines. It produces intelligence, but it produces idiocy and
cretinism for the worker. K Marx, Early Writings, op cit, p325
Human
beings are social beings. We have the ability to act collectively to further
our interests. However, under capitalism that ability is submerged under
private ownership and the class divisions it produces. We have the ability to
consciously plan our production, to match what we produce with the developing
needs of society. But under capitalism that ability is reversed by the anarchic
drive for profits. Thus, rather than consciously shaping nature, we cannot
control, or even foresee, the consequences of our actions. For example, new,
cheaper techniques of production may, when repeated across industry, produce
acid rain or gases which destroy the ozone layer.
Similarly,
when one capitalist improves production in his factory, he is unwittingly
contributing to the creation of surplus in market (Harman, 1995). This means
that we produce more but what we produce is unwanted. All previous societies
suffered from shortages, famines and the failure of crops. Under capitalism
recessions mean that workers consume less, not because their labour is
inadequately productive, but because their labour is too productive'. There is
nothing natural about the economic crises we face: it is our social
organisation which prevents us enjoying the potential of our ability to
produce.
White collar employees
The American sociologist C. Wright Mills conducted a major study of alienation in modern society with "White Collar" in 1951, describing how modern social division of labor, involve a hitherto unknown specialization of skill: as a proportion of the labor force, fewer individuals manipulate things, more handle people and symbols. This shift in needed skills is another way of describing the rise of the white-collar workers, for their characteristic skills involve the handling of paper and money and people. They are masters of the commercial, professional, and technical relationship. They live off the social machineries that organize and co-ordinate the people who do make things. White-collar people help turn what someone else has made into profit.
False consciousness
The concept “False consciousness” refers to the systematic misrepresentation of dominant social relations in the consciousness of subordinate classes. Marx himself did not use the phrase “false consciousness,” but he paid extensive attention to the related concepts of ideology and commodity fetishism. Members of a subordinate class (workers, peasants, serfs) suffer from false consciousness in that their mental representations of the social relations around them systematically conceal or obscure the realities of subordination, exploitation, and domination those relations embody. Related concepts include mystification, ideology, and fetishism.
Marx
offered an objective theory of class, based on an analysis of the objective
features of the system of economic relations that constitute the social
order. A person's social class is
determined by his or her position within the system of property relations that
constitutes a given economic society. People also have subjective
characteristics: thoughts, mental frameworks, and identities. These mental
constructs give the person a cognitive framework in terms of which the person
understands his or her role in the world and the forces that govern his or her
life. One's mental constructs may
correspond more or less well to the social reality they seek to represent. In a
class society, there is an inherent conflict of material interests between
privileged and subordinate groups(Little, 2007). Marx
asserts that social mechanisms emerge in class society that systematically
creates distortions, errors, and blind spots in the consciousness of the
underclass. If these
consciousness-shaping mechanisms did not exist, then the underclass, always a
majority, would quickly overthrow the system of their domination. So the institutions that shape the person’s
thoughts, ideas, and frameworks develop in such a way as to generate false
consciousness and ideology.
Marx’s
theory of ideology is presented in The German
Ideology (Marx and Engels [1845-49] 1970).
Marx uses the term “ideology” to refer to a system of ideas through
which people understand their world. A
central theoretical assertion in Marx’s writings is the view that “ideology”
and thought are dependent on the material circumstances in which the person
lives. Material circumstances determine
consciousness, rather than consciousness determining material reality: “The
hand-mill gives you society with the feudal lord; the steam-mill society with
the industrial capitalist” (Marx 1971).
A system of ideology plays the role of supporting the class advantage of
the dominant class, according to Marxist theory. The concept of commodity fetishism is
discussed in Capital (Marx 1977). Marx
uses this concept to refer to the pervasive and defining illusion that exists
in a commodity society. A commodity is
perceived solely in terms of its money equivalent (its price), rather than
being understood as standing within a set of social relations of
production. Marx believes that this is
a socially important form of mystification; the market society erases the relations
of domination and exploitation on which it depends.
Twentieth-century Marxist thinkers have given more systematic attention to a Marxist theory of consciousness and ideology. Georg Lukács introduces the concept of false consciousness into Marxist discourse, based on a brief reference by Engels, in relation to a dialectical theory of knowledge.
However,
the dialectical method does not permit us simply to proclaim the ‘falseness’ of
this consciousness and to persist in an inflexible confrontation of true and
false. On the contrary, it requires us to investigate this ‘false
consciousness’ concretely as an aspect of the historical totality and as a
stage in the historical process. Lucacs noted
« consciousness is not only to comprehend the relations of exploitation
in society, but is to acknowledge the class historic role. For Marx class
consciousness is a ‘practical critical activity’ with the task of ‘changing the
world’. The historically significant actions of the class as a whole are
determined in the last resort by this consciousness. The fate of a class depends on its ability to
elucidate and solve the problems with which history confronts it……
Ideologically the same growth of insight into
the nature of society entails a steady growth in the strength of the
proletariat. For the proletariat the truth is a weapon that brings victory.
Consciousness approaches society from another world and leads it from the false
path it has followed back to the right one. Nevertheless, the bonds connecting
the immediate life-interests of the proletariat with society as a whole have
not even begun to penetrate its consciousness.
The consciousness of the proletariat is still fettered by reification.
The reified consciousness becomes a completely passive observer moving in
obedience to laws which it can never control…» (Lukacs, 1971).
A
more sociological treatment of class consciousness was provided by Karl
Mannheim in his effort to formulate a sociology of knowledge in the 1930s
(Mannheim 1959 [1936]). The sociology of
knowledge attempts to provide a theoretical account of the relationship between
knowledge systems and the social conditions within which they emerge; this
provides a theoretical framework in terms of which to understand the workings
of a system of ideology. Mannheim
supports the idea that the social position of the bourgeoisie and the
proletariat deeply influence the forms of knowledge that they embody; and in
each case, he argues that these forms of material bias lead to a systematic
falsification of social reality.
Antonio
Gramsci significantly extended Marxist thinking about ideology and
consciousness in the 1930s (Gramsci 1971).
Gramsci gave ideology a more active role in politics and history than
classical historical materialism. He
argued that the proletariat has the ability to influence the terms of its
consciousness, so there is an extended struggle between the bourgeoisie and the
proletariat over the terms of the representation of the existing social
reality. The bourgeoisie generally
exercises “hegemony” over the terms of ideology, through its control of the
instruments of consciousness; but the proletariat can exert influence through
its own cultural institutions. This
perspective introduces a major change into the classical theory of ideology, in
that it denies that the subordinate class is simply the passive tool of the
dominant ideology.
Fromm working firmly within the “ideology as false
consciousness” perspective, observed that through “a complicated process of
indoctrination, rewards, punishments, and fitting ideology most people believe
they are following their own will and are unaware that their will itself is
conditioned and manipulated.” For him, learning
to penetrate ideological obfuscation, and thereby overcoming the alienation
this obfuscation induced, was the learning task of adulthood.
Frantz Fanon: Alienation and colonianism
Frantz Fanon, an early writer on postcolonialism, studied the conditions of objectification and violent oppression (lack of autonomy) believed to have led to mental disorders among the colonized in the Third World (in particular Africans) (Fanon, 1961).
Fanon sees the alienation of the colonized, as essentially socio-economic, but it is a socio-economic (socio-political) alienation that has profound psychological effects. He speaks about the alienation of the Negro in terms of cultural imposition, and of the exploitation of the native by the colonists.
He locates alienation equally firmly in the
imperialist division of the world into poor countries and rich, exploiters and
exploited, rulers and ruled. Psychological violence then becomes a form of
cultural imperialism in the context of the colonial situation…its victim is an
alienated person, in the strong
institutions developed over centuries by
the colonizers.
The alienation of the
native may take the form of assimilation, the loss of cultural identity or its
disruption, through which the social group imitate the oppressor. Within this
context, Fanon writes:
‘’The oppressor,
through the inclusive and frightening character of his authority, manages to
impose on the native new ways of seeing, and in particular, a pejorative
judgment with respect to his original forms of existing’’.
Fanon’s
social theory extends Marx’s concept of alienation to the analysis of how race
is constructed and reproduced within colonialism. His theory asserts that race,
like class, is a denial of our species-being. Our humanity is a function of
being recognized by others in a social relationship: Man is human only to the extent
to which he is being recognized by another man. It is on recognition by that
other being, that his own human worth and reality depend. It is that other
being in whom the meaning of his life is condensed (Fanon 1967).
Colonialism is not simply the economic exploitation and political domination of the periphery by the capitalist core. It is also the separation of colonized peoples from their individuality and culture (Fanon 1961).
Colonized
peoples are denied the opportunity to know themselves. Instead, the colonizer
claims to ‘know’ the colonized, but this knowledge “betrays a determination to
objectify, to confine, to imprison” (Fanon 1968). The rich history and
institutions of the indigenous population are physically and symbolically
destroyed, and in their place the colonizer produces a people who deserve only
to be ruled. The colonizer constructs colonized peoples as ‘lazy’ and
‘unproductive,’ thereby justifying low wages or coercive systems of labor. He
also constructs them as ‘stupid,’ thereby justifying the imposition of the
colonial power’s institutions and practices. Finally, he constructs them as
‘savage’ and ‘dangerous,’ thereby justifying military conquest and coercive
forms of social control. The result is a people “in whose soul an inferiority
complex has been created by the elimination of its local cultural originality”
(Fanon 1967).
Racism and its objectification of the colonized, Fanon argues, can only be understood through its connection to capitalism. The colonial relationship between core and periphery in global capitalism is, like that between capitalist and proletariat, based on exploitation/
Epistemological
approaches
For Lacan, alienation is an
inescapable part of identity. Put differently, to be a subject is to be
alienated. To this effect, in a tellingly entitled chapter ‘The Subject and
Other: Alienation’, he (1981) proposes two types of alienation as precipitated
by the presence of a Big Other, a figure who ostensibly represents
psychological fullness. The first is contained in the very ‘decision’ to become
a subject, through entering into a prevailing symbolic discourse. The
possibility of psychic fullness, or of overcoming our innate sense of lack,
through the symbolic command of a Big Other is inalterably alienating. Secondly
this alienation persists even after one enters into the symbolic order. The
‘Real’ of who one is forever escapes the symbolic meanings culturally provided
by a Big Other. Accordingly, one is by nature alienated, in that one defies
symbolic signification.
Figures associated
with critical theory, in particular with
the Frankfurt School1, such as Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, Erich
Fromm and Jürgen Habermas, also developed
theories of alienation, drawing on neo-Marxist ideas as well as other
influences including neo-Freudian and sociological theories. They applied
Marxist theories of commodification to the cultural, educational and
party-political spheres. Links are drawn between socioeconomic structures,
psychological states of alienation, and personal human relationships. This
critical program could be contrasted with a tradition of linear studies that
attempt to extract problems of alienation from the broader socioeconomic
context, and which often attribute problems to individual abnormality or
failures to adjust (Pangilinan, 2009).
Critical
theory recognizes that culture is as much a determinant of the form of society
as political economy. Any change in the form of society will ultimately have
economic and political effect but it cannot be achieved without transformation
of the culture of modernity. The form of society has a material dimension: the
economic and practical arrangements for meeting needs, the laws governing
social actions and the specific institutions that make practical arrangements.
But the material form of society is given meaning, communicated and understood
through the society’s culture: the ideas, understanding, reasons, images,
writing and other modes of expression that accompany the material dimension.
Frankfurt School critical theory mounts its critique of society as culture,
rather than as political system or economy. Culture is treated not simply as
the artistic and communicative stuff of society but as the way that ordinary
lives are lived: at work, at leisure, through sexuality, as consumers, as minds
that are curious and seek to be entertained, as social subjects that are
knowing and have an interest in the way society is organized.
The Dialectic of Enlightenment by Max
Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno
published in 1947 can certainly be considered as one of the most influential
works of Frankfurt School.
The theme of alienation is a leitmotif of this
book. Alienation is not only an aspect of the labour markets anymore, but is
noticeable in a wide range of aspects of society like e.g. such as the substitution
of character by function, the cycle of manipulation and need, of leadership of mass culture, and mass media.
Horkheimer and Adorno noticed the development of individuals becoming totally subordinated by the economic powers. The question of the character of man is mainly the question of his or her function in society in general and in the economic system in particular. That is what we can call the substitution of character by function.
In the industrialised
world, marked by the division of labour, every function within the system is
predefined by the task that is to be fulfilled by the single individual. The
defined function itself seems not to leave room for the special individual
character but forces the character to adjust to the demands of the role it has
to take. Thus, the single individual becomes substitutable (and consumable), since everyone will at least adjust. This
has a two-folded consequence. First: The alienation of oneself. And second: The
equalisation of individuals. Since the adjustment to the pre-existing system of
work and economy seems desperately necessary to survive, the unfolding of the
single character becomes marginal and many people tend to define themselves
just by their success in the everyday competition of life. What’s left from the
human character is the ability to develop skills which are useful for the
system. That makes at least everybody equal. In the Human Resources Departments
of the today’s big companies thousands of applications pile up that can mainly
be distinguished by names but mostly look the same. Even the phrase Human
Resource expresses the limitation of the single employee to a resource for the
system and society. The ability to alienate from oneself is still and again
becomes more and more necessary for being a successful and acknowledged part of
society.
Another noticeable
aspect, that Horkheimer and Adorno pick up in this context, is the use of
rationality in today’s world. This seems to be affirmed, if one e.g. takes a
look on the domination of the concept of homo economicus in social science, the
domination of economics at all and the downfall of aspects like philosophical
education and critical theoretical thinking.
Moreover the
individual in modern capitalistic society is not just a substitutable resource
but as well a substitutable consumer, who is caught in a “cycle of manipulation
and need”.
At this point
Horkeheimer and Adorno connect the sphere of economy with the sphere of modern
mass culture. Through the influence of radio, TV and today the internet as well
people get connected to a undifferentiated mass of consumers of industrial
products as well as consumers of culture itself. Yet the consumer only
consumes, if he feels a need to do so. The point is, that the capitalistic
system can only keep up itself by steady growth. Therefore on the on hand it is
necessary to produce and offer new products almost every day and on the other
hand it is necessary to build up a need for these products. At least in
industrialised countries all basic needs of humans are almost totally
satisfied, like needs for food, for clothing, for living room, etc.. If we e.g.
consider the pyramid of needs by US-Psychologist Abraham Maslow only the basic
needs of a human can finally be satisfied by industrial products. Non-basic
needs like social acknowledgement or self-development can hardly be satisfied
by the economy. Therefore it seems logical, that, when basic needs are
fulfilled, the only way to achieve sustainable economic growth is by creating
constantly new, but after all artificial needs. These needs are often build up
just by offering a new product.
Finally generating an artificial need for something is a kind of manipulation and so the people get trapped in this so called cycle of manipulation and need. Mass media and culture now is one way to fortify this cycle. The interesting and finally dialectic aspect of this cycle is, what Horkheimer and Adorno also state, that by offering people this kind of mass culture with a lots of choices, it is pretended that capitalist society offers a never seen before freedom for people. But finally it is a just illusory freedom without real alternatives. The freedom is limited to the choice of buying just different sorts of the ever-same. This illusion “of competition and choice” is held up high by the mass media using advertisement and entertaining to keep people at it.
That leads to a direct influence on society. We again come to the point of the character of man. On the one hand it was stated, that it is build up by the role he or she adjusts to in society, on the other hand character is often build up and indicated to the outside world by what one does and what one has. By the clothing one wears he or she mostly automatically indicates belonging to a social group, may it be a group marked by financial status, wearing e.g. luxury brands, or a group marked by an ideological or not seldom musical background, e.g. wearing “hip-hop-style” clothing or Gothic clothing, etc.. But finally showing a belonging to a group by using products produced in the cycle of manipulation and need restrains the categories of character to choose from to a maybe high but still limited number. Individuality is pseudo-individuality. Thus, finally the capitalistic economic system offers us a kind of matrix of possibilities we can fit ourself in, but real freedom remains illusionary. The human will always be just a member of a group, limited in choices. Within this group his character is only in limited ways individual, if it is at all.
The alienation the human being in modern mass society runs through is a dialectic of adjustment and equalisation on the one side and of isolation on the other side.
By becoming a just “functioning part” of society, blunted by the phenomenon of mass culture and the use of an almost mere technological rationality, people loose the ability for real sociality. In Education after Auschwitz Adorno criticises in a very similar way the loss of the ability to love. People become monads, struggling in the social coldness and atmosphere of competition and hostility of everyday life. Alienation becomes finally an all-embracing phenomenon. People are alienated of each other and are trapped in a capitalistic cage, being a mass, which can be directed, e.g. using mass media. Individual critical thinking was substituted by the already described mere technological rationality. Thus, by mass culture and the capitalistic economical system the cornerstone for the fascistic and totalitarian system is laid. Since society was not more than an accumulation of monads, being indifferent against the individual, e.g. the use of technological rationality for realizing a system of industrialised mass murder became eventually possible. The rationality, born by the Enlightenment, reversed itself into the contrary. In Education after Auschwitz Adorno raises the question, how it otherwise could be possible, that e.g. a well-educated engineer uses his knowledge to construct a railway-system for the deportation of Jews to Concentration Camps. This finally was a consequence of alienation from oneself and others.
But today’s society
is still marked by the same phenomenons which Horkheimer and Adorno described
1947, mass culture and capitalism, which seem not least to lead to a steady and
ongoing depoliticization of people. Thus, maybe it is the prosperity of
democracy or maybe just the consciousness about history that prevents us from
totalitarianism.
Jürgen
Habermas' ‘’Theory
of Communicative Action’’ attempts a change of paradigm to the theory of communication makes it
possible the critique of instrumental reason; and this renewed the task of a
critical theory of society. Jürgen
Habermas understands language as the foundational component of society. He
attempts to update Marxism by "drawing on Systems theory (Luhmann),
developmental psychology (Piaget, Kohlberg), and social theory (Weber, Durkheim,
Parsons, Mead, etc.)". Alienation
stems from the distortion of reasoned moral debate by the strategic dominance
of market forces and state power.
"Modern
structures of consciousness emerged from the universal historical process of
world-view rationalisation, that is, from the disenchantment of
religious-metaphysical world views."
At the same time the means of production including that of culture
increasingly passed into the control of a new class. (Who source of wealth is
through ownership of the means of production).
The result is the promotion of a 'purposive rational action' in all spheres. An action orientated to profit and power rather than understanding, arising from entrepreneurial capitalism.
According to Weber,
rationalisation creates three spheres of value: the differentiated zones of
science, art and law. "The transition to modernity is characterised by a differentiation
of spheres of value and structures of consciousness that make possible a
critical transformation of traditional knowledge. For Habermas, this fundamental
disunity of reason constitutes the danger of modernity. This danger arises not
simply from the creation of separate institutional entities but through the
specialisation of cognitive, normative, and aesthetic knowledge that in turn
permeates and fragments everyday consciousness. This disunity of reason implies
that culture moves from a traditional base in a consensual collective endeavour
to forms which are rationalised by commodification and led by individuals with
interests which are separated from the purposes of the population as a whole. This 'purposive rational action' is
steered by the "media" of the state, which substitute for oral language
as the medium of the coordination of social action.
"The
socio-psychological costs of a rationalisation restricted to the cognitive
instrumental dimension - costs that are externalised by society and shifted to
individuals - appear in different guises, ranging from clinically treated
mental illnesses through neuroses, phenomena of addiction, pyschosomatic
distrubances, educational and motivational problems, to the protest actions of
aesthetically inspired countercultures, religious youth sects and marginal
criminal groups and religious cults."
Lukacs
specific achievement consists in bringing Marx and Weber together in such a way
that he can view the decoupling of the sphere of social labour from lifeworld2
contexts simultaneously under two aspects: as reification and
rationalisation... He conceives of the reification of lifeworld contexts, which
set in when workers coordinate their interactions by way of the
de-linguistified medium of exchange value rather than through norms and values,
as the other side of a rationalisation of their action orientations."
Habermas, in contrast
to Adorno and Horkheimer, thinks that freedom and ideals of reconciliation are
ingrained in the mechanisms of the linguistically mediated sociation of
humanity. His pragmatic optimism
contrasts with other critical theorists. We can see from Weber through Lukacs
to Adorno that thinkers have agreed that the rationalisation of society has
produced a reification of consciousness.
Habermas
then defines communicative action as a type of speech act in which the
participants 'pursue illocutionary aims' 'first and foremost'. "He mean to
distinguish cases of communications motivated by egocentric calculations of
success from communications orientated to understanding. Further only those illocutionary acts to
which actors connect validity claims' are constitutive of communicative action.
Modern second-order cybernetics is a paradigm that offer a holistic picture of the constantly emerging novel complexities of ongoing human interaction, and does not postulate simplistic assumptions about the constancy of human behavior. The result of the adoption of the systemic paradigm, is that alienation studies, are becoming less denunciatory, less normative, and moralistic (Geyer, 1998).
Complexity is in the structure rather than in the elements making up the
structure, in the way simple building blocks are organized as a result of
simple laws. It is indeed the vastly more complex forms of human organization,
and the increased interdependence of human organizations, rather than the
increased complexity of human individuals themselves that has promoted the
modern forms of alienation. Growing interdependence implies increasing communication.
The
emergence of complexity is a bottom-up process, without any central controller
leading it, rather than a top-down one; it is a matter of local units, acting
according to local laws, producing new levels of complexity by interacting.
It
is indeed difficult to maintain that the complexity of the modern world is
somehow ordained from above; while interaction may sometimes result in
hierarchization, these hierarchies are again local units when engaging in a
wider process of globalization.
Life
is not a property of matter, but of organization of matter. Living systems are
constructed from the bottom up.
On
the contrary, top-down systems are forever running into combinations of events
they do not know how to handle.
The world is becoming more complex and
interdependent, that consequently causal chains stretch further geographically
and timewise. The process of
complexification is irreversible.
The pathology of alienation
the five prominent features of alienation,
Melvin Seeman
Melvin Seeman in his
paper, "On the Meaning of
Alienation" (1959), used the insights of Marx, Emile Durkheim and
others to construct a model to recognize the five prominent features of
alienation: powerlessness, meaninglessness, normlessness, isolation and
self-estrangement (Seeman, 1959).
Powerlessnes
Alienation in the
sense of a lack of power has been technically defined by Seeman as “the
expectancy or probability held by the individual that his own behaviour cannot
determine the occurrence of the outcomes, or reinforcements, he seeks."
Put more succinctly, Kalekin-Fishman (1996) says, “A person suffers from alienation
in the form of 'powerlessness' when she is conscious of the gap between what
she would like to do and what she feels capable of doing”.
Meaninglessness
Seeman (1959) writes
that meaninglessness “is characterized by a low expectancy that satisfactory
predictions about the future outcomes of behaviour can be made." Where as
powerlessness refers to the sensed ability to control outcomes, this refers to
the sensed ability to predict outcomes. In this respect, meaninglessness is
closely tied to powerlessness; Seeman argues, “the view that one lives in an
intelligible world might be a prerequisite to expectancies for control; and the
unintelligibility of complex affairs is presumably conducive to the development
of high expectancies for external control (that is, high powerlessness)”.
Geyer (1996) believes
meaninglessness should be reinterpreted for postmodern times: "With the
accelerating throughput of information [...] meaningless is not a matter
anymore of whether one can assign meaning to incoming information, but of
whether one can develop adequate new scanning mechanisms to gather the
goal-relevant information one needs, as well as more efficient selection
procedures to prevent being overburdened by the information or the so-called
"data tsunami" one does not need, but is bombarded with on a regular
basis."
Normlessness
Normlessness (or what
Durkheim referred to as anomie) “denotes the situation in which the social
norms regulating individual conduct have broken down or are no longer effective
as rules for behaviour”.[24] This aspect refers to the inability to identify
with the dominant values of society. Seeman (1959) adds that this aspect can
manifest in a particularly negative manner, “The anomic situation may be
defined as one in which there is a high expectancy that socially unapproved
behaviours are required to achieve given goals”. This negative manifestation is
dealt with in detail by Catherine Ross and John Mirowski (2001) in a series of
publications on mistrust, powerlessness, normlessness and crime.
Neal & Collas
(2000) write, “Normlessness derives partly from conditions of complexity and
conflict in which individuals become unclear about the composition and
enforcement of social norms. Sudden and abrupt changes occur in life
conditions, and the norms that usually operate may no longer seem adequate as
guidelines for conduct”. This is a particular issue of the mass migrations, and
the general sense of disillusionment that characterized the 1990s (Senekal,
2011). Traditional values that had already been questioned (especially during
the 1960s) were met with further scepticism in the 1990s, resulting in a
situation where individuals rely more often on their own judgement than on
institutions of authority: "The individual has become more independent of
the churches, and from other social institutions and can make more personal
choices in far more life situations than before” (Halman, 1998). These choices
are not necessarily "negative": Halman's study found that Europeans
remain relatively conservative morally, even though the authority of the Church
and other institutions has eroded.
One manifestation of
the above dimensions of alienation can be a feeling of estrangement from, and a
lack of engagement in, the political system. Such political alienation could result
in abstention from the political process, and political apathy (Schwartz, 2007)
.
Social isolation
Social isolation
refers to “The feeling of being segregated from one’s community”. Neal and
Collas (2000) emphasize the centrality of social isolation in the modern world:
“While social isolation is typically experienced as a form of personal stress,
its sources are deeply embedded in the social organization of the modern world.
With increased isolation and atomization, much of our daily interactions are
with those who are strangers to us and with whom we lack any ongoing social
relationships.”
Self-estrangement
Self-estrangement is
an elusive concept in sociology, as recognized by Seeman (1959), although he
included it as an aspect in his model of alienation. Self-estrangement can be
defined as “the psychological state of denying one’s own interests – of seeking
out extrinsically satisfying, rather than intrinsically satisfying,
activities...”. It could be characterized as a feeling of
having become a stranger to oneself, or to some parts of oneself, or
alternatively as a problem of self-knowledge, or authenticity.Seeman (1959) recognized the problems inherent in defining the "self", while post-modernism in particular has questioned the very possibility of pin-pointing what precisely "self" constitutes. Gergen (1996) argues that: “the traditional view of self versus society is deeply problematic and should be replaced by a conception of the self as always already immersed in relatedness. On this account, the individual’s lament of ‘not belonging’ is partially a by-product of traditional discourses themselves”. If the self is relationally constituted, does it make sense to speak of "self-estrangement" rather than "social isolation"?
Mental disturbance
Until early in the
20th century, psychological problems were referred to in psychiatry as states
of mental alienation, implying that a person had become separated from
themselves, their reason or the world. From the 1960s alienation was again
considered in regard to clinical states of 'schizoid'' and splitting' disturbances.
Varied concepts of alienation and self-estrangement were used to link internal
schizoid states with observable symptoms and with external socioeconomic
divisions. R.D. Laing was particularly influential in arguing that
dysfunctional families and socioeconomic oppression caused states of alienation
and ontological insecurity in people, which could be considered adaptations but
which were diagnosed as disorders by mainstream psychiatry and society (Laing,
1967). For Laing, alienation is
characterized by neglect and distance from an individual’s self-experience and
self-identity, and by a lack of autonomy in interpersonal relations (heteronomy). He argues that people who
are diagnosed with disorders such as attention deficit disorder and schizophrenia are
often suffering from a more sociological condition - ontological insecurity.
Laing was one of the most articulate critics of the stance in which “the clinician assumes a priori that he is a neutral scientific observer/classifier of an (irrational) patient’s speech and behavior.”
Laing’s,
ideas are relevant in the light of inability of modern psychiatry to think
sociologically and critically about the concept of normality as well as the
one-sided dominance of the medical model in mental health (Burston,2000).
Laing’s
early work was devoted to “elucidating the dilemmas of the schizoid and
schizophrenic patient.” Drawing on Gregory’s Bateson’s famous concept of the
“double-bind,” Laing suggested that, “a patient’s bizarre ideas and utterances
are often intelligible responses to the complex and contradictory messages,
demands, and prescriptions imposed on them by others.” In his most
well-known book The Politics of
Experience (1967), Laing expanded this critique of normality in modern
society to suggest, “families, schools, and churches provide us with little
more than systematic training in self-estrangement and inauthenticity”.
Laing must be understood as part of a larger tradition that has raised important questions about the social construction of sanity and about the need for a theory and therapeutic practice that puts un-measurable qualities such as human hope, fears, evil and even spiritual well-being at the center of any psychological approach in the human sciences and helping professions.
Within
sociology, theorists such as Erving Goffman, Michel Foucault, Thomas Scheff,
Dorothy Smith and various scholars have been raising similar concerns about how
definitions of mental illness can be socially, organizationally and politically
constructed (Burston,2000).
The larger questions that Laing
raises are as relevant as ever. There is a politics to therapy, and it cannot
be understood simply as a technical and medical issue, despite the claims of
some mental health professionals. Should psychotherapists take political stands
in relation to the society in which they work? Is helping patients adapt to
society a political stand itself? Is the
rise of drug-based therapies a move away from the humanism of Psychotherapeutic
tradition, as well as a capitulation to the logic of insurance companies, a
consequence of a modern culture concerned with quick fixes and a victory for
pharmaceutical companies fixated on profits? Reasonable questions can be raised
about the rights of individuals who do not fall within the definitions of
normality laid out with such certitude in documents such as the Diagnostic and
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders.
For Ian Parker, psychology normalizes
conditions of social alienation. While it could help groups of individuals
emancipate themselves, it serves the role of reproducing existing conditions
(Parker, 2007). This view can be seen as part of a broader tradition sometimes
referred to as Critical psychology or Liberation psychology, which emphasizes
that an individual is enmeshed within a social-political framework, and so
therefore are psychological problems. Similarly, some psychoanalysts suggest
that while psychoanalysis emphasizes environmental causes and reactions, it
also attributes the problems of individuals to internal conflicts stemming from
early psychosocial development, effectively divorcing them from the wider
ongoing context.
Fromm suggests
that “the insane person is the absolutely alienated person” who has lost a sense
of self and cannot situate him/herself as the center of his/her own
experiences. He suggests that as people become alienated, they lose their
understanding of themselves and do not see their experiences as being based on
their own decisions, judgments, and actions. Alienated people lead meaningless
lives; they are estranged from themselves, others, and society. Fromm considers
alienation almost complete in modern capitalist societies, and explains that it
pervades individuals’ consumption habits as well as their relationships to
their work, to their communities, to their fellow citizens, and to themselves.
An alienated person lacks a sense of reality regarding “the meaning of life and
death, for happiness and suffering, for feeling and serious thought.” In a
technological age, machines routinely replace human intelligence and citizens
tend to manipulate symbols and other people rather than actively and creatively
producing commodities. They are not invested in their work, and find it
routine, boring, and dull, which further contributes to a sense of apathy and
dissatisfaction with their lives. As Fromm explains, in contemporary society
work often can be defined “as the performance of
acts which cannot yet be performed by machines.” Within alienated societies
consumption now dominates and defines the culture. Citizens consume food,
drink, news, and entertainment without any active participation or unifying
experiences resulting from the consumption. In addition, a continuous, ever
expanding need for consumption is encouraged by “artificially stimulated
fantasies” (Fromm, 1955) created by advertising and a variety of other
psychological pressures that coax individuals into repeatedly buying as much as
they can.
In a related vein, Slavoj
Zizek (drawing on Herbert Marcuse, Michel Foucault, and Jacques Lacan) argues
that in today's capitalist society, the individual is estranged from their self
through the repressive injunction to "enjoy!" Such an injunction does
not allow room for the recognition of alienation and, indeed, could itself be
seen as an expression of alienation.(Zizek, 1994).
Zizek points out
(2007) “The so-called permissive society allows all enjoyments, thus enjoyment
is limited more than ever, as if there was a command that one can enjoy
everything – on the premise that the
substance that makes them dangerous has been removed ( decaffeinated coffee, foods
without fats, etc). There is an
abundance of all earthly pleasures ( from educational lectures to groups about
the orthopedic of relations ) offered by the current culture to fill the
leisure. All these provide material to the subject to forget the existence and
death and also to disregard in a false communication the special meaning of
life” (Zizek, 2007).
Contemporary alienation
Following the flowering of contestation movements at sixties and student revolutions in Europe and the USA, alienation studies proliferated, at least in the Western world. The existence of alienation in the ‘decadent, bourgeois’ societies of the West was confirmed, as it was supposed to herald the impending demise of late capitalism.
During the 1980s, as the postwar baby boomers4 grew older,
and perhaps more disillusioned, and willynilly entered the rat race, interest
in alienation subsided.
Nowadays stress is, on
describing new forms of alienation increasingly pervasive ethnic alienation and
conflict, and on alienation as caused by high joblessness rates, living under
conditions of extreme economic deprivation an abject political system,
exploitative working conditions, etc.
The changing
nature in public employment policy, competition and the supposed end of
‘careers’ and lifetime job security, has driven employees in a continuous race
to obtain achievements, titles, skills personal
capacities that make them more likely to gain employment and be able to move between jobs, thus
remaining employable throughout their life.
This contemporary trend of the
present working reality, has been called employability.
Employability; purportedly provides individuals the
resources to not only obtain employment but also, more importantly, the
opportunity to ‘control their employment fate’. Consequently, employability
points to the emergence of an empowering contemporary identity juxtaposed against
a changing economic reality that is marked by even greater job insecurity (Bloom, 2013).
Perhaps the option, to be one able to define one’s working destiny, that
employability promises has been proclaimed as the solution of overcoming
alienation-without changing the relations of production.
Yet, employability, deepens the employee’s commitment to capitalist
ideologies and managerial demands (Cremin, 2010).. At the heart of this desire
for employability, organizations’ wish to cultivate a culture in which the
authority of management is re-established through the creation of a committed,
yet autonomous, workforce (Costea et al., 2007).
Cremin (2010) introduces the
concept of ‘reflexive exploitation’ connected to employability, whereby ‘a
person reflects on herself as an object of exchange in order to access a wage
and social status, to choose a life that is compatible with the injunctions of
liberal capitalism’ (Cremin, 2010).
Employability
stands as a hegemonic discourse structuring identity around the paradox of self-mastery, within an admittedly
alienating capitalist reality Actually the result is the deeper colonization of
subjectivity in line with capitalist values (Bloom,
2013). Identity centers here on the capitalist desire
to maximize one’s profit from exploitation.
These insights point, to the ways an empowering identity can be
ironically constructed so as to actually reflect dominant demands and
understandings. Acquiescing to hegemonic values is made more palatable when
clothed in an appealing sheen of empowerment and resistance.
A new determinant of alienation has emerged,
which is the result of, unmanageable environmental complexity. In much of the Western world, the average
person is increasingly confronted, on a daily basis, with an often bewildering
and overly complex environment, which promotes attitudes of political apathy,
often politically dangerous oversimplification of complex political issues, and
equally dysfunctional withdrawal from wider social involvements (Geyer, 2001).
What is clear is that modern forms of
alienation are emerging and will affect increasing numbers of people in the
developed world, and soon also in the developing world. Several authors have
hinted at this development. Lachs (1976) spoke of a mediated world, where the
natural cycle of action/feedback is
broken, and where one is less and less in command of more and more of the things
that impinge on one’s life. Etzioni (1968) likewise saw alienation as resulting
from nonresponsive social systems that do not cater to basic human needs. Toffler
(1970, 1990) vividly described how change is happening not only faster around
us, but even through us.
Coping
alienation
The above mentioned Bloom’s analysis of employability, seeks to provide the foundations for moving beyond this fantasy of employability. Recently, a number of critical scholars within the field have theorized the relation of fantasy to resistance. Hoedemaekers (2010), for example, calls on subjects to pay attention to such ‘interruptions’ to identification as potential sites for transversing, or break free from, a prevailing fantasy. Similarly, Contu (2008), inspired by Žižek, promotes a form of resistance by which individuals are willing to engage in acts that defy the symbolism and enjoyment associated with their current identities. Specific to discourses of employability, Cremin (2010) suggests to construct new fantasies and therefore selves which reject ideologies of managerialism and exploitation in favour of new values. Indeed, this appears to be happening the world over, as struggles in the wake of the financial crisis, such as the occupy movement or those catalyzed by the European debt crisis, in which new ‘commons’ are emerging reconfiguring identity work in relation to ideals of greater social and economic freedom and democracy.
Major changes in the world as globalization and the computer science and technology revolution have brought to the fore new productive forces and changes in relations of production and explosion of societal complexity and worldwide interdependence.
Modern technology greatly
empowers individuals to perform tasks through control over the equivalent of
large armies of slaves (Yaneer, 1997). These increased abilities could lead to
independent and self-sufficient individuals, each providing for his or her own
needs. A new possibility appears to be
happening—the formation of networks of interdependent individuals.
An empowerment of individuals,
by the development of tools, results in an increasing complexity of
activity. The diverse individual
activities are difficult to control because it is impossible for an individual
to know how to control and coordinate many diverse activities. At the same time, the coordination of
activities through a network becomes possible through advances in
communication.
Complexity as all the
phenomenon of life is ambiguous. From one side it is forming the modern aspects
of alienation but at the other, attenuates the centralization of control and
manipulation.
Thus, we can extract from it that the quantity
that can be tied most directly to a loss of effectiveness of central control is
complexity. (Yaneer,
1997).
FOOTNOTES
1 In
a more focused sense, critical theory designates several generations of German
philosophers and social theorists in the Western European Marxist tradition
known as the Frankfurt School, which is particularly associated with the
Institute for Social Research at the University of Frankfurt am Main. In order
to fill in the perceived omissions of traditional Marxist thought, the Frankfurt
School theorists sought to draw answers from other schools of thought, hence
using the insights of psychoanalysis, Weberian theory, aesthetic modernism and
other disciplines. The school’s main figures attempted to overcome the limits
of positivism, materialism and determinism by returning to Immanuel Kant’s
critical philosophy and its successors in German idealism. Hegel’s philosophy,
with its emphasis on dialectic and contradiction as inherent properties of
reality. In a nutshell, the theorists of the Frankfurt School aimed a radical
transformation of the social world of advanced capitalism that will bring
freedom for all from features of modern society that restrict or constrain
individuals from living in freedom. It does not aim to bring about social
change through revolutionary means, through confronting the practical and
economic arrangements with political opposition.
2 Lifeworld: the social processes that reproduce
cultural traditions, social integration, and personal identities. In lifeworld, we construct, maintain and
refresh meanings .
3Illocutionary pertaining to a linguistic act performed by a speaker in producing an utterance, as suggesting, warning, promising, or requesting. Illocutionary act is a term in linguistics introduced by the philosopher John L. Austin in his investigation of the various aspects of speech acts. For example, in uttering the locution "Is there any salt?" at the dinner table, one may thereby perform the illocutionary act of requesting salt, as well as the distinct locutionary act of uttering the interrogatory sentence about the presence of salt, and the further perlocutionary act of causing somebody to hand one the salt.
According to Austin's original exposition in
How to Do Things With Words, an illocutionary act is an act (1) for the
performance of which I must make it clear to some other person that the act is
performed (Austin speaks of the 'securing of uptake'), and (2) the performance
of which involves the production of what Austin calls 'conventional consequences'
as, e.g., rights, commitments, or obligations (Austin 1975, 116f., 121, 139).
Thus, for example, in order to make a promise I must make clear to my audience
that the act I am performing is the making of a promise, and in the performance
of the act I will be undertaking an obligation to do the promised thing.
Searle
(1975) set up the following classification of illocutionary speech acts:
directives
= speech acts that are to cause the hearer to take a particular action, e.g.
requests, commands and advice
commissives
= speech acts that commit a speaker to some future action, e.g. promises and
oaths
expressives
= speech acts that express on the speaker's attitudes and emotions towards the
proposition, e.g. congratulations, excuses and thanks
declarations
= speech acts that change the reality in accord with the proposition of the
declaration, e.g. baptisms, pronouncing someone guilty or pronouncing someone
husband and wife
4 Baby boomers are people born during the demographicPost-World War II baby boom, between the years 1946 and 1964. According to the
U.S. Census Bureau, the term "baby boomer"
is also used in a cultural context.
Baby boomers are associated with
a rejection or redefinition of traditional values; however, many commentators
have disputed the extent of that rejection, noting the widespread continuity of
values with older and younger generations. In Europe and North America boomers
are widely associated with privilege, as many grew up in a time of widespread
government subsidies in post-war housing and education, and increasing
affluence.
One feature
of the boomers was that they tended to think of themselves as a special
generation, very different from those that had come before. In the 1960s, as
the relatively large numbers of young people became teenagers and young adults,
they, and those around them, created a very specific rhetoric around their
cohort, and the change they were bringing about. This rhetoric had an important
impact in the self perceptions of the boomers, as well as their tendency to
define the world in terms of generations, which was a relatively new
phenomenon.
References
Arthur, M.
B. and D. M. Rousseau (2001) The boundaryless career: A new employment
principle for a new organizational era. New York: Oxford University Press.Bloom Peter (2013) Fight for your alienation: The fantasy of employability and the ironic struggle for self-exploitation. Ephemera volume 14, number 4 November,
Bloom, P.
and C. Cederström (2009) ‘The sky’s the limit: Fantasy in the age of market
rationality’, Journal of Organizational Change Management, 22(2): 159-190.
Braverman
H, Labour and Monopoly Capitalism (Monthly Review Press, 1974),
Burston Daniel (2000)
The Crucible of Experience: R.D. Laing and the Crisis of Psychotherapy
Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2000,
Costea, B.,
N. Crump and K. Amiridis (2007) ‘Managerialism and “infinite human
resourcefulness”: A commentary upon the “therapeutic habitus”, “derecognition
of finitude” and the modern sense of self’, Journal of Cultural Research,
11(3): 245-264.
Cox
Judy 1998 An introduction to Marx's
theory of alienation Issue 79 of INTERNATIONAL SOCIALISM, quarterly journal of the
Socialist Workers Party (Britain) Published July 1998 Copyright © International Socialism
http://pubs.socialistreviewindex.org.uk/isj79/cox.htmCremin, C. (2010) ‘Never employable enough: The (im)possibility of satisfying the boss’s desire’, Organization, 17(2): 131-149.
Elias N 1939 Uber den Prozess der Zivilisation. Haus
zum Falken, Basel
Etzioni A
1968 The Active Society. Collier-Macmillan, LondonFanon Frantz (1961), The Wretched of the Earth: A Negro Psychoanalyst’s Study of the Problems of Racism & Colonialism in the World Today. 1961 (New York, New York: Grove Press, Inc.)
Fanon,
Frantz. 1967. Black Skin, White Masks. New York: Grove Press.
Fanon,
Frantz. 1968a. Toward the African Revolution. New York: Grove Press.Fischer E, (1996) How to Read Karl Marx (Monthly Review Press, 1996)
Fromm,
Erich (1955) The Sane Society (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston,
Geyer Felix
(1998) Sociocybernetics and the new alienations. Paper presented in World
Congress of Sociology, Montreal, July 26- August 1, 1998Geyer Felix (2001) Alienation, Sociology of in International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, Paul Baltes and Neil Smelser, Eds., London: Elsevier Durkheim Alienation, Sociology of
Ghoshal,
S., C. Bartlett and P. Moran (1999) ‘A new manifesto for management’, Sloan
Management Review, 40(spring): 9-20.
Gramsci,
Antonio. 1971. Selections from the Prison Notebooks of Antonio Gramsci.
Translated by Q. Hoare and G. Nowell-Smith. New York: International.
Habermas,
Jürgen (1984) [1981]. Theory of Communicative Action Volume One: Reason and the
Rationalization of Society (Book). Translated by Thomas A. McCarthy. Boston,
Mass.: Beacon Press
Hall, D.T.
(2002) Careers in and out of organizations. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Halman,
Loek. 1998. "Family patterns in contemporary Europe:
Results from the European Values Study 1990". In Kalekin-Fishman, Devorah (ed.). Designs for Alienation: Exploring Diverse Realities. Finland: University of Jyväskylä.
Harman C,
Economics of the Madhouse (Bookmarks, 1995) Horkheimer Max, Adorno W. Theodor (1947) Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments Stanford University Press,
Hoedemaekers,
C. (2009) ‘Traversing the empty promise: management, subjectivity and the
Other’s desire’, Journal of Organizational Change Management, 22(2): 181-201.
Horkheimer, Max / Adorno, Theodor (2008): Dialektik der
Aufklärung. 17th edition. Frankfurt a.M... P.4.
Kalekin-Fishman, D. 1996. Tracing the growth of
alienation: enculturation, socialization, and schooling in a democracy. (In
Geyer, F., ed. Alienation, ethnicity and postmodernism. London: Greenwood. p.
95-106.)
Lacan, J.
(2001) Ecrits: a selection, trans. Bruce Fink. New York: W.W. Norton and
Company.
Lachs J
1976 Mediation and psychic distance. In: Geyer F,Schweitzer D (eds.) Theories
of Alienation—Critical Perspectives in Philosophy and the Social Sciences.
Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, pp. 151–67
Laing R. D.
(1967) The Politics of Experience (1967), publ.
Routledge & Kegan Paul.Linebaugh P, The London Hanged (Penguin, 1993)
Little, Daniel. 2007. “False
Consciousness,” in William A. Darity, Jr., ed. International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences second edition. New York: Macmillan. UnderstandingSociety
Ludz P 1975 ‘Alienation’ als Konzept der
Sozialwissenschaften. Kolner Zeitschrift fur Soziologie 27(1): 1–32WWLukács, G. (1971) History and class consciousness. London: Merlin Press
Lukács, György. 1971 [1920]. History and class consciousness; studies in Marxist dialectics. Cambridge, Mass.,: MIT Press.
Mannheim, Karl. 1959 [1936]. Ideology and utopia : an introduction to the sociology of knowledge, A harvest book ; HB 3. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Marx K,
Capital, vol 1 (Penguin, 1976)
Marx K,
Early Writings (Penguin, 1975)
Marx, Karl,
and Friedrich Engels. [1845-49] 1970. The German ideology. 3d rev. ed. Moscow:
Progress Publishers.
Marx, Karl.
1971. The Poverty of Philosophy. Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, Karl.
1977. Capital. Vol. 1. New York: Vintage.
Mills, C.
Wright, (1951) White collar; the American middle classes New York : Oxford
University Press
Neal, A.G. & Collas, S.F. 2000. Intimacy
and alienation: forms of estrangement in female/male relationships. New
York: Garland.
Newman, Michael, Defining the Enemy: Social
Action in Adult Education (Sydney: Stewart Victor, 1994)
<http://www.michaelnewman.info/docs/ defining_the_enemy.pdf>, 16 March
2009).
Ollman B,
Alienation (Cambridge University Press, 1996)
Pangilinan
Rafael D. (2009) Against Alienation: The Emancipative Potential of Critical
Pedagogy in Fromm Kritike, Vol3, No2 Rafael D.
Parker Ian 2007 Revolution in Psychology:
Alienation to Emancipation Pluto press London
Roberts, J.
(2005) ’The power of the “imaginary” in disciplinary processes’, Organization,
12(5): 619-642.
Ross, Catherine E., John Mirowski and Shana Pribesh, 2001: Powerlessness
and the Ampli-fication of Threat: Neighborhood Disadvantage, Disorder, and
Mistrust, American Sociological Review, 66: 568-591.
Rubin I I,
Essays on Marx's Theory of Value (Black Rose Books, 1975)
Schaar,
John, (1961) Escape from Authority: The Perspectives of Erich Fromm (New York:
Basic Books,).
Schwartz C. David 2007 Political Alienation and Political Behavior Transaction Publishers, 30 Apr 2007 David C. Schwartz Political Alienation and Political Behavior Transaction Publishers, 30 Apr 2007
Seeman M.
(1959) On the meaning of alienation. Amer. Sociol. Rev. 24:783-91, 1959.
[University of California, Los Angeles, CA]
Toffler A
1970 Future Shock. Bantam Books, New
York
Toffler A
1990 Power Shift—Knowledge, Wealth and Violence at the Edge of the 21st
Century. Bantam Books, New York
Yaneer
Bar-Yam (1997) Dynamics of Complex Systems Addison-Wesley
Žižek, S.,
(1997). The plague of fantasies. London: Verso.
Žižek, S.,
2007 En defensa de la intolerancia, Madrid: Sequitur.
Δεν υπάρχουν σχόλια:
Δημοσίευση σχολίου